new posts in all blogs
Viewing: Blog Posts Tagged with: descartes, Most Recent at Top [Help]
Results 1 - 11 of 11
How to use this Page
You are viewing the most recent posts tagged with the words: descartes in the JacketFlap blog reader. What is a tag? Think of a tag as a keyword or category label. Tags can both help you find posts on JacketFlap.com as well as provide an easy way for you to "remember" and classify posts for later recall. Try adding a tag yourself by clicking "Add a tag" below a post's header. Scroll down through the list of Recent Posts in the left column and click on a post title that sounds interesting. You can view all posts from a specific blog by clicking the Blog name in the right column, or you can click a 'More Posts from this Blog' link in any individual post.
By: John Priest,
on 10/2/2016
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
René Descartes,
western philosophy,
european philosophy,
early modern cartesianism,
early modern philosophers,
early modern philosophy,
european philosophers,
Henricus Regius,
Henricus Regius philosopher,
Principia Philosophiæ,
Regius,
tad schmaltz,
descartes,
*Featured,
Cartesians,
Arts & Humanities,
early modern,
cartesian philosophers,
cartesian philosophy,
Philosophy,
Add a tag
Regius was a professor of medicine at the University of Utrecht. He was much taken with the views he had read in the scientific essays accompanying Descartes’s Discours de la méthode (1637), and was one of the first to introduce Descartes’s new mechanistic account of the material world into the Dutch academy.
The post Cartesian plasticity: The curious case of Henricus Regius appeared first on OUPblog.
By: John Priest,
on 8/13/2016
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
quiz,
Philosophy,
Multimedia,
philosophers,
descartes,
*Featured,
POTM,
René Descartes,
Quizzes & Polls,
western philosophy,
Arts & Humanities,
Philosophy Quiz,
philosopherotm,
potm quiz,
philosopherotm quiz,
european philosophy,
descartes quiz,
philosopher quiz,
Add a tag
This August, the OUP Philosophy team honors René Descartes (1596–1650) as their Philosopher of the Month. Called “The Father of Modern Philosophy” by Hegel, Descartes led the seventeenth-century European intellectual revolution which laid down the philosophical foundations for the modern scientific age.
The post How much do you know about René Descartes? [quiz] appeared first on OUPblog.
By: John Priest,
on 7/31/2016
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
17th century philosophy,
european philosophy,
french philosophy,
potm timeline,
Philosophy,
timeline,
descartes,
Timelines,
*Featured,
interactive timeline,
POTM,
René Descartes,
Arts & Humanities,
Philosopher of the Month,
philosopherotm,
philosophy timeline,
Discourse on Method,
Meditations on First Philosophy,
Add a tag
This August, the OUP Philosophy team honors René Descartes (1596–1650) as their Philosopher of the Month. Called “The Father of Modern Philosophy” by Hegel, Descartes led the seventeenth-century European intellectual revolution which laid down the philosophical foundations for the modern scientific age. His philosophical masterpiece, the Meditations on First Philosophy, appeared in Latin in 1641, and his Principles of Philosophy, a comprehensive statement of his philosophical and scientific theories, also in Latin, in 1644.
The post Philosopher of the month: René Descartes appeared first on OUPblog.
By: Samantha Zimbler,
on 11/21/2015
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
Biography,
Philosophy,
Meditations,
descartes,
Pythagoras,
*Featured,
René Descartes,
Online products,
Oxford Bibliographies,
oxbibs,
Adrien Baillet,
Ausonius,
Cartesian method,
Descartes dreams,
Discourse on Method,
Justin Skirry,
Meditations on First Philosophy,
Nebraska Wesleyan University,
Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy,
Ulm,
Add a tag
On a blustery St. Martin’s Eve in 1619, a twenty-three year old French gentleman soldier in the service of Maximilian of Bavaria was billeted near Ulm, Germany. Having recently quit his military service under Maurice of Nassau, he was new to the Bavarian army and a stranger to the area.
The post The phosphene dreams of a young Christian soldier appeared first on OUPblog.
By: Alex Guyver,
on 6/21/2015
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
Books,
Philosophy,
Locke,
brain,
consciousness,
mind,
descartes,
John Locke,
*Featured,
philosophy of the mind,
Arts & Humanities,
Locke's Touchy Subjects,
mind-body problem,
Nicholas Jolley,
Add a tag
At one point in the recent film The Imitation Game the detective assigned to his case asks Alan Turing whether machines could think. The dialogue that follows is perhaps not very illuminating philosophically, but it does remind us of an important point: the computer revolution that Turing helped to pioneer gave a huge impetus to interest in what we now call the mind-body problem. In other words, how is the mind related to the body? How could a soggy grey mass such as the brain give rise to the extraordinary phenomenon of consciousness?
The post How is the mind related to the body? appeared first on OUPblog.
By: RachelM,
on 9/15/2014
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
Books,
ethics,
Philosophy,
physics,
logic,
descartes,
Humanities,
metaphysics,
*Featured,
Physics & Chemistry,
Science & Medicine,
René Descartes,
Cartesians,
Descartes and the First Cartesians,
Frans Hans,
Principles of Philosophy,
Roger Ariew,
the Cartesian System,
Add a tag
René Descartes wrote his third book, Principles of Philosophy, as something of a rival to scholastic textbooks. He prided himself in ‘that those who have not yet learned the philosophy of the schools will learn it more easily from this book than from their teachers, because by the same means they will learn to scorn it, and even the most mediocre teachers will be capable of teaching my philosophy by means of this book alone’ (Descartes to Marin Mersenne, December 1640).
Still, what Descartes produced was inadequate for the task. The topics of scholastic textbooks ranged much more broadly than those of Descartes’ Principles; they usually had four-part arrangements mirroring the structure of the collegiate curriculum, divided as they typically were into logic, ethics, physics, and metaphysics.
But Descartes produced at best only what could be called a general metaphysics and a partial physics.
Knowing what a scholastic course in physics would look like, Descartes understood that he needed to write at least two further parts to his Principles of Philosophy: a fifth part on living things, i.e., animals and plants, and a sixth part on man. And he did not issue what would be called a particular metaphysics.
Descartes, of course, saw himself as presenting Cartesian metaphysics as well as physics, both the roots and trunk of his tree of philosophy.
But from the point of view of school texts, the metaphysical elements of physics (general metaphysics) that Descartes discussed—such as the principles of bodies: matter, form, and privation; causation; motion: generation and corruption, growth and diminution; place, void, infinity, and time—were usually taught at the beginning of the course on physics.
The scholastic course on metaphysics—particular metaphysics—dealt with other topics, not discussed directly in the Principles, such as: being, existence, and essence; unity, quantity, and individuation; truth and falsity; good and evil.
Such courses usually ended up with questions about knowledge of God, names or attributes of God, God’s will and power, and God’s goodness.
Thus the Principles of Philosophy by itself was not sufficient as a text for the standard course in metaphysics. And Descartes also did not produce texts in ethics or logic for his followers to use or to teach from.
These must have been perceived as glaring deficiencies in the Cartesian program and in the aspiration to replace Aristotelian philosophy in the schools.
So the Cartesians rushed in to fill the voids. One could mention their attempts to complete the physics—Louis de la Forge’s additions to the Treatise on Man, for example—or to produce more conventional-looking metaphysics—such as Johann Clauberg’s later editions of his Ontosophia or Baruch Spinoza’s Metaphysical Thoughts.
Cartesians in the 17th century began to supplement the Principles and to produce the kinds of texts not normally associated with their intellectual movement, that is treatises on ethics and logic, the most prominent of the latter being the Port-Royal Logic (Paris, 1662).
By the end of the 17th century, the Cartesians, having lost many battles, ultimately won the war against the Scholastics.
The attempt to publish a Cartesian textbook that would mirror what was taught in the schools culminated in the famous multi-volume works of Pierre-Sylvain Régis and of Antoine Le Grand.
The Franciscan friar Le Grand initially published a popular version of Descartes’ philosophy in the form of a scholastic textbook, expanding it in the 1670s and 1680s; the work, Institution of Philosophy, was then translated into English together with other texts of Le Grand and published as An Entire Body of Philosophy according to the Principles of the famous Renate Descartes (London, 1694).
On the Continent, Régis issued his General System According to the Principles of Descartes at about the same time (Amsterdam, 1691), having had difficulties receiving permission to publish. Ultimately, Régis’ oddly unsystematic (and very often un-Cartesian) System set the standard for Cartesian textbooks.
By the end of the 17th century, the Cartesians, having lost many battles, ultimately won the war against the Scholastics. The changes in the contents of textbooks from the scholastic Summa at beginning of the 17th century to the Cartesian System at the end can enable one to demonstrate the full range of the attempted Cartesian revolution whose scope was not limited to physics (narrowly conceived) and its epistemology, but included logic, ethics, physics (more broadly conceived), and metaphysics.
Headline image credit: Dispute of Queen Cristina Vasa and René Descartes, by Nils Forsberg (1842-1934) after Pierre-Louis Dumesnil the Younger (1698-1781). Public domain via Wikimedia Commons.
The post The construction of the Cartesian System as a rival to the Scholastic Summa appeared first on OUPblog.
By: Sara Pinotti,
on 7/20/2014
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
Books,
Philosophy,
body,
consciousness,
mind,
descartes,
Humanities,
*Featured,
dualism,
colin mcginn,
determinism,
actual consciousness,
actualism,
epiphenomenalism,
philosophy of mind,
ted honderich,
honderich,
dilmen,
nevit,
Add a tag
By Ted Honderich
The philosopher Descartes set out to escape doubt and to find certainties. From the premise that he was thinking, even if falsely, he argued to what he took to be the certain conclusion that he existed. Cogito ergo sum. He is as well known for concluding that consciousness is not physical. Your being conscious right now is not an objective physical fact. It has a nature quite unlike that of the chair you are sitting on. Your consciousness is different in kind from objectively physical neural states and events in your head.
This mind-body dualism persists. It is not only a belief or attitude in religion or spirituality. It is concealed in standard cognitive science or computerism. The fundamental attraction of dualism is that we are convinced, since we have a hold on it, that consciousness is different. There really is a difference in kind between you and the chair you are sitting on, not a factitious difference.
But there is an awful difficulty. Consciousness has physical effects. Arms move because of desires, bullets come out of guns because of intentions. How could such indubitably physical events have causes that are not physical at all, for a start not in space?
Some philosophers used to accomodate the fact that movements have physical causes by saying conscious desires and intentions aren’t themselves causal but they go along with brain events. Epiphenomenalism is true. Conscious beliefs themselves do not explain your stepping out of the way of joggers. But epiphenomenalism is now believed only in remote parts of Australia, where the sun is very hot. I know only one epiphenomenalist in London, sometimes seen among the good atheists in Conway Hall.
A decent theory or analysis of consciousness will also have the recommendation of answering a clear question. It will proceed from an adequate initial clarification of a subject. The present great divergence in theories of consciousness is mainly owed to people talking about different things. Some include what others call the unconscious mind.
But there are also the criteria for a good theory. We have two already — a good theory will make consciousness different and it will make consciousness itself effective. In fact consciousness is to us not just different, but mysterious, more than elusive. It is such that philosopher Colin McGinn has said before now that we humans have no more chance of understanding it than a chimp has of doing quantum mechanics.
There’s a lot to the new theory of Actualism, starting with a clarification of ordinary consciousness in the primary or core sense as something called actual consciousness. Think along with me just of one good piece of the theory. Think of one part or side or group of elements of ordinary consciousness. Think of consciousness in ordinary perception — say seeing — as against consciousness in just thinking and wanting. Call it perceptual consciousness. What is it for you to perceptually conscious now, as we say, of the room you’re in? Being aware of it, not thinking about it or something in it? Well, the fact is not some internal thing about you. It’s for a room to exist.
It’s for a piece of a subjective physical world to exist out there in space — yours. That is something dependent both on the objective physical world out there and also on you neurally. A subjective physical world’s being dependent on something in you, of course, doesn’t take it out of space out there or deprive it of other counterparts of the characteristics you can assemble of the objective physical world. What is actual with perceptual consciousness is not a representation of a world — stuff called sense data or qualia or mental paint — whatever is the case with cognitive and affective consciousness.
That’s just a good start on Actualism. It makes consciousness different. It doesn’t reduce consciousness to something that has no effects. It also involves a large fact of subjectivity, indeed of what you can call individuality or personal identity, even living a life. One more criterion of a good theory is naturalism — being true to science. It is also philosophy, which is greater concentration on the logic of ordinary intelligence, thinking about facts rather than getting them. Actualism also helps a little with human standing, that motive of believers in free will as against determinism.
Ted Honderich is Grote Professor Emeritus of the Philosophy of Mind and Logic at University College London. He edited The Oxford Companion to Philosophy and has written about determinism and freedom, social ends and political means, and even himself in Philosopher: A Kind of Life. He recently published Actual Consciousness.
Subscribe to the OUPblog via
email or
RSS.
Subscribe to only philosophy articles on the OUPblog via
email or
RSS.
The post What is consciousness? appeared first on OUPblog.
By: ChloeF,
on 4/4/2014
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
Religion,
meditation,
Philosophy,
VSI,
Zen,
Very Short Introductions,
william james,
mindfulness,
consciousness,
mind,
descartes,
threads,
*Featured,
dualism,
Psychology & Neuroscience,
conscious,
mind-body,
Sue Blackmore,
Susan Blackmore,
chalmers,
chiming,
blackmore,
consciousness’,
Add a tag
By Susan Blackmore
The problem of consciousness is real, deep and confronts us any time we care to look. Ask yourself this question ‘Am I conscious now?’ and you will reply ‘Yes’. Then, I suggest, you are lured into delusion – the delusion that you are conscious all the time, even when you are not asking about it.
Now ask another question, ‘What was I conscious of a moment ago?’ This may seem like a very odd question indeed but lots of my students have grappled with it and I have spent years playing with it, both in daily life and in meditation. My conclusion? Most of the time I do not know what I was conscious of just before I asked.
Try it. Were you aware of that faint humming in the background? Were you conscious of the birdsong? Had you even noticed the loud drill in the distance that something in your brain was trying to block out? And that’s just sounds. What about the feel of your bottom on the chair? My experience is that whenever I look I find lots of what I call parallel backwards threads – sounds, touch, sights, that in some way I seem to have been listening to for some time – yet when I asked the question I had the odd sensation that I’ve only just become conscious of it.
Back in 1890 William James (one of my great heroes of consciousness studies) remarked on the sounds of a chiming clock. You notice the chiming after several strikes. At that moment you can look back and count one, two, three, four and know that now it has reached five. But it was only at four that you suddenly became conscious of the sound.
William James
What’s going on?
This, I suggest, is just one of the many curious features of our minds that lead us astray. Whenever we ask ‘Am I conscious now? we always are, so we leap to the conclusion that there must always be something ‘in my consciousness’, as though consciousness were a container. I reject this idea. Instead, I think that most of the time our brains are getting on with their amazing job of processing countless streams of information in multiple parallel threads, and none of those threads is actually ‘conscious’. Consciousness is an attribution we make after the fact. We look back and say ‘This is what I was conscious of’ and there is nothing more to consciousness than that.
Are we really so deluded? If so there are two important consequences: One spiritual and one scientific.
Many contemplative and mystical traditions claim we are living in illusion; that we need to throw off the dark glasses of the false self who seems to be in control, who seems to have consciousness and free will; that if we train our minds through meditation and mindfulness we can see through the illusion and live in clearly awareness right here and now. I am most familiar with Zen and I love such sayings as, ‘Actions exist and also their consequences but the person that acts does not’. Wow! Letting go of the person who sees, thinks, and decides is not a trivial matter and many people find it outrageous that one would even want to try. Yet it is quite possible to live without assuming that you are consciously making the decisions – that you are a persisting entity that has consciousness and free will.
From the scientific point of view, throwing off these illusions would totally transform the ‘hard problem of consciousness’. This is, as Dave Chalmers, the Australian philosopher, describes it, the question of ‘how physical processes in the brain give rise to subjective experience’. This is a modern version of the mind-body problem. Almost everyone who works on consciousness agrees that dualism does not work. There cannot be a separate spirit or soul or persisting inner self that is something other than ordinary matter. The world cannot be divided, as Descartes famously thought, into mind and matter – subjective and objective, physical material and mental thoughts. Somehow the two must ultimately be one – But how? This ‘nonduality’ is what mystical traditions have long described, but it is also the hope that science is grappling with.
And something strange is happening in the science of consciousness. The last few decades have seen fantastic progress in neuroscience. Yet paradoxically this makes the problem of consciousness worse, not better. We now know that decisions are initiated in part of the frontal lobe, actions are controlled by areas as far apart as the motor cortex, premotor cortex and cerebellum, visual information is processed in multiple parallel pathways at different speeds without ever constructing a picture-like representation that could correspond to ‘the picture I see in front of my eyes’. The brain manages all these amazing tasks in multiple parallel processes. So what need is there for ‘me’? And what need is there for subjective experience? So what is it and why do we have it?
Perhaps inventing an inner conscious self is a convenient way to live; perhaps it simplifies the brain’s complex task of keeping us alive; perhaps it has some evolutionary purpose. Whatever the answer, I am convinced that all our usual ideas about mind and consciousness are false. We can throw them off in the way we live our lives, and we must throw them off if our science of consciousness is ever to make progress.
Susan Blackmore is a freelance writer, lecturer and broadcaster, and a Visiting Professor at the University of Plymouth. She is the author of Consciousness: A Very Short Introduction.
The Very Short Introductions (VSI) series combines a small format with authoritative analysis and big ideas for hundreds of topic areas. Written by our expert authors, these books can change the way you think about the things that interest you and are the perfect introduction to subjects you previously knew nothing about. Grow your knowledge with OUPblog and the VSI series every Friday, subscribe to Very Short Introductions articles on the OUPblog via email or RSS, and like Very Short Introductions on Facebook.
Subscribe to the OUPblog via email or RSS.
Subscribe to only psychology articles on the OUPblog via email or RSS.
Image credit: Public domain, via Wikimedia Commons
The post A question of consciousness appeared first on OUPblog.
By: Keith Mansfield,
on 9/25/2011
Blog:
Keith Mansfield
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
Science,
Opera,
CERN,
Descartes,
Albert Einstein,
relativity,
speed of light,
Feynman Diagrams,
imaginary numbers,
michelson-Morley,
nonlinear filtering,
special relativity,
Add a tag
The science and even the popular press are filled with excitement at the moment after the OPERA experiment at Europe’s giant particle physics laboratory, CERN (to which I applied for a summer job when I was 16, but that’s another story). Apparently, neutrinos sent from CERN and captured at Italy’s INFN Gran Sasso Laboratory about 730 km away are arriving faster than scientists thought physically possible – faster than the speed of light travelling in a vacuum.
I had to write about this because the news reporting has really annoyed me. Every announcement has said that Einstein might be wrong because he (special relativity) says nothing can travel faster than light in a vacuum. Poppycock! (As I’m being polite.) What the theory says is that nothing that has what scientists call “rest mass” can travel at the speed of light – there isn’t any block on things travelling faster. It’s always slightly surprised me that in a discipline where mathematical physicists are used to things called discontinuous functions, I rarely hear of people willing to accept that something could go from “slower” to “faster” without having to “equal”, but it might be possible.
One argument against travelling faster than light is that, although there are solutions to Einstein’s equations, they contain the square root of minus one which we sometimes call an “imaginary” number (as opposed to other numbers that are called “real”). This is a brilliant example of mathematical spin and how it has actually damaged our understanding of mathematics and the universe. There is nothing less real about these imaginary numbers than what are called the real ones. It’s actually by combining both set that we achieve a far deeper understanding of the mathematical and physical universe. But way back when they were first introduced, French mathematician and philosopher Rene Decartes was very distrustful of them so coined the term imaginary as a pejorative description, hoping it would mean they didn’t catch on. He’s got a lot to answer for.
What is a neutrino? Like the similarly named neutron, a neutrino carries no net electric charge (compared with other familiar subatomic particles such as electrons (-1) or protons (+1). Unlike the neutron, the neutrino has almost (but not quite) no mass. Having no charge and almost no mass makes a neutrino extremely difficult to detect.
Back to relativity! Anything travelling faster than light in relativity yields solutions including the square root of minus one which people have interpreted as meaning travelling backwards in time. That’s the reason for the joke that’s currently doing the rounds on the twittersphere:
Barman: “I’m sorry, sir. We don’t serve neutrinos in here.”
A neutrino walks into a bar.
By:
MsLuhks,
on 3/3/2011
Blog:
Amsco Extra!
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
Conventions,
Philosophy,
Descartes,
Open-ended,
History of Mathematics,
Right-hand Rule,
Quadrants,
Clockwise,
Coordinate Plane,
Graphing,
Add a tag
|
The Cartesian Plane |
In the new national
Common Core Learning Standards, mathematics students in 5th grade begin to explore graphing in the first quadrant (where the values of each coordinate are positive), and in 6th grade expand to all four quadrants of the plane. The appearance of
the coordinate plane at this early time in the curriculum emphasizes its importance for the study of mathematics. The plane is the brain-child of René Descartes, prominent 17th-century French philosopher and mathematician. (That’s why we also call it the
Cartesian plane.)
Two perpendicular lines, the
x-axis and the
y-axis, split the plane into four infinite quarter-planes, which are called quadrants. As mentioned earlier, the first quadrant has positive values for both its
x and
y coordinates. Quadrants are numbered using Roman numerals, so we label it I. Then we label the other quadrants, naming them with Roman numerals II, III, and IV, in counterclockwise order. As shown in the graph, QII has negative
x-values, but positive
y-values. QIII has negative
x-values and negative
y-values. QIV has positive
x-values, but negative
y-values. Even as, more and more frequently, time presents itself digitally, some students may wonder why the quadrants are not arranged clockwise. Some may be initially confused. For others, even if it makes sense at first, a clockwise orientation may feel more natural, and the draw of the familiar may provide an opportunity for error.
Teachers should expect to be questioned about this: “Why not clockwise?” The stock answer is, “That’s the rule.” Take the time to delve a little deeper. This response may sound to a young person like, “because I say so.” Dissatisfaction with explanations and confusion about them go hand in hand. A solid understanding of how to label the quadrants should enable your students to discuss graphing more efficiently. Graphing on the coordinate plane is a skill that will be immensely valuable throughout high school math and well into college courses, including and beyond multi-variable calculus and electro physics. The purpose of this convention and most conventions in general, is to avoid ambiguity. (And ambiguity can lead to chaos! Imagine if we didn’t have the convention of driving on only one side of the road.)
Physicists in particular use the
right-hand rule to navigate in three dimension
What is a book worth?
What is the value of a book? Maybe in this instance it might be best to ask - how am I defining value.
Worth to an individual ? Absolute intrinsic value ...